toward a definition of art
The definition of art has always been
unstable and conflicted. To some the
label implies excellence, excluding doggerel of poetasters or the films of Ed
Wood and Herschel Lewis. Yet, apart from
the fact that aesthetic value cannot be proven, it cannot be part of the
definition or the expression “good art” would be redundant. For much of the past many critics used a
nearly class-based standard, admitting works of “high art,” while excluding
folk art, popular, and mass forms. Since
the Romantics discovered folksong, however, this notion has withered, until now
public media and such once august organs as the New York Times devote a
good deal of their coverage to topics like Taylor Swift and new series from
Netflix.
One way to
approach a definition is to distinguish art from similar phenomena occupying
neighboring semantic territory, what might be termed “para-aesthetic phenomena.” Surveying all the arts, through the centuries
and around the globe, the qualities that are generally considered to contribute
to the definition of art often include the following.
1.
Art is a form of play involving manipulated symbols arranged and
generally preserved for repeated consumption.
2. Art is beautiful. Qua art, it has no other function, though
it may be incidentally susceptible to other uses.
3.
In part the beauty of art is achieved through formal or structural
patterns.
4.
Art refracts lived reality, intentionally shaping the raw material of
experience into significant fictions.
Among the
non-aesthetic forms of play are sports and games, as well as child’s play and
make-believe. Yet the footballer or the
broad-jumper are dealing in physical challenges and not symbols, and the child,
whether solitary or in a group, plays for the moment without a thought of preserving
the fantasy for later visits. The chief
distinguishing characteristic of our species is the ability to manipulate
symbols, and humans enjoy exercising this skill just as the lion relishes the
pounce. Verbal repartee may be artful,
but, if not transcribed, would not be art.
The player of video games is constantly making decisions simply for the
fun of it, but the drama vanishes as
soon as the play ends. The maker of such
a game game would have a stronger claim on the title of artist, though most
critics would find such work too trivial to allow the maker entrance to
Parnassus. Certain works, such as true
“happenings” or the sand paintings made by both Navajos and Tibetans, are
likewise ephemeral, but in such cases the violation of the usual convention
calls perhaps even greater attention to it.
A more precise formulation of the nature of art is required to define
the frontiers of the aesthetic, but one may begin by thinking of objets
d’art as artifacts of preserved play.
Art is universally,
though only in part, defined by the quality of beauty. For a definition of beauty, Santayana’s
formulation will do: beauty is “pleasure regarded as the quality of a thing.” Yet many things can give us pleasure. Good news, a gourmet meal, or a fulfilling
sexual encounter may bring considerable pleasure and yet would not usually be
considered art. Still, some non-aesthetic
pleasures include characteristics of art.
Cuisine is often considered a sort of minor art as the cook must make
many decisions based on taste and the whole meal is presented to the diner as a
coherent progression, an experience to some extent unified. Sexual activity likewise may well present a
series of actions, a sort of play, designed to make a designed effect, but they
are scarcely designed for the consumption of anyone other than the participants. Other attributes of art must be taken into
account to sharpen the focus more tightly.
Much of the
beauty of art is based of structural or formal patterns. The simplest and most commonly invoked are
unity and symmetry, but disunity and asymmetry may find an equally important
place in certain circumstances. Formal
qualities are always present, but they are most obvious in genres like music
and abstract visual art. A fugue by Bach
or a Rothko canvas derive their power largely from their consumers’
apprehension of such abstract patterns.
Yet abstraction is virtually never absolute. The mind strives to make sense of written
lines and visual forms like a child looking for shapes in the clouds. Even a totally random arrangement will be
read as having meaning. In addition this
formal standard is not unique to works of art.
People also judge how pleasant it is to gaze at non-aesthetic objects,
the faces of others, for instance, based on similar criteria. While formal beauty may be found in a variety
of phenomena where its presence is a matter of chance, it is intentionally
created by artistic design
Art typically
conveys a theme, that is, it suggests certain aspects of lived experience. Vulgarly, this is the familiar “moral of the
story,” often the focus of classroom investigations through secondary school
and beyond. Though technically the work
of art asserts no more than the proposition that “at one time the world may
have some seemed like this to someone,” such themes are often (sometimes doubtless
with justice) taken to represent the opinions of the author. In contrast to the ancient trope claiming
that art “imitates” reality, most contemporary critics would prefer to
acknowledge that art always alters the raw material of which it is made, making
such terms as “transforming” or “refracting” more accurate. Of course, dreams, news stories and familiar
letters also relate versions of lived experience without pretensions to
artistic value.
Since each of the
defining characteristics of art present in non-aesthetic experiences as well,
the judgement of whether a given object is or is not art becomes probabilistic,
likelier as the evidence mounts. A
further complication arises since art may be used in non-aesthetic ways. For instance, a philologist may in the texts
of Homer find evidence for linguistic development or a historian data for the
study of ancient religion, but such researches are incidental and unrelated to
the artistic value of the Iliad. Likewise,
non-art may be received as though it were aesthetic experience by the
appreciator of photographs from the Webb telescope or of fractal patterns.
Art does not
exist without humans; it is socially constructed, not natural. The very concept of art has not existed
in all cultures. For those who recognize the category, there will
always remain disputed boundaries. While
most work that pretends to the status of art must probably be admitted,
regardless of value, most of the questions pertain to semi-art knocking on the door from
outside. An essay on flowers or
fiddlesticks will scarcely be questioned by the gatekeepers of the club of art,
while an essay about that essay will be relegated to mere criticism, though it
may be as beautifully written, as indeed in theory might an essay on electrical
engineering. If one admits Maxfield
Parrish and Normal Rockwell to museum status, is all illustration art? Do the journalistic war reports of Hemingway
and Ernie Pyle hold aesthetic value? How
about A. J. Liebling and Red Smith’s sports stories? Style in dress may sometimes suggest a refraction of reality. Journal entries and sketchbook
improvisations are not usually intended to outlast the day of their creation,
yet, once preserved, may, like the jottings of Pepys and Picasso, be highly
valued. Religious myth and liturgy,
while clearly composed of narrative and drama, claim other primary uses. Art’s definition is worth pursuing even if it
cannot be precisely and finally formulated.
Art is, as well, dynamic, and will evolve even under study.
No comments:
Post a Comment