A dramatic
performance is aptly called a play, though a sonnet or a sonata might deserve
the name no less. All art is a form of
play, though not all play is art. When
goat kids tussle and cats knock a ball around, they are playing. Their end is amusement, just as opera-goers
and sonnet-readers are pleasantly passing the time, though art aficionados
might call what they are seeking beauty.
All are enjoying recreation in a diversion from the pursuit of practical
goals. The dog slavering while pursuing
a stick and the gallery visitor cocking a discerning eye have a good deal in
common.
Play might be
defined as activity done for its own sake without any function other than the
satisfaction arising from the act itself.
Throughout the centuries those defending the arts from moralists who
regarded aesthetic pursuits as frivolous or hedonistic have maintained that
exposure to aesthetic objects makes the consumer more noble and more moral,
but, should it ever happen, this effect is incidental. The same is true of more modest claims that
art increases sympathy or sensitivity, or, indeed, that its study benefits
general intelligence. While it is true
that art encodes and transmits cultural values and spiritual convictions, this
function, too, is nonessential. Pleasure
is the chief and essential end of art, though critics yet today, in an odd
vestige of moralism, shrink from admitting it.
This week’s New
York Times Opinion section, for instance, includes the promise that the
study of art will “improve your taste, your judgements, your conduct.” [1] The notion that culture will sharpen both
cognitive and moral discernment, while broad and unqualified, seems modest when
juxtaposed to the article’s extravagant title “How to Save a Sad, Lonely, Angry
and Mean Society,” Such claims are
likely to be in part defensive, reacting to today’s educational stress on
science and devaluation of humanities.
For centuries of
European criticism had accepted a compromise in the authoritative formula
“delight and instruct,” with the second term justifying and diluting the
first. Yet recognition of people’s
fondness for symbolic representation
goes back to Aristotle who recognized this distinctive human taste, saying
“from childhood to imitate is inborn in people and in this they differ from other animals,” since
“by nature we have an instinct for representation.” The contemplation of such symbols or representations
or “imitations” in Aristotle’s term, brings us “pleasure.” [2] in
the Politics Aristotle is quite clear about the uselessness of art,
saying that the young must not be taught skills that are merely functional (he
uses the term χρήσιμος, useful or serviceable), as his activities should not be
corrupted by what is “not free” (ἀνελεύθερος),
This is, of course the basis for the value long placed on the “liberal
arts,” those of free men, unbound by compulsion, wages, or practical ends.
[3] This sort of disinterested pastime is
a self-justifying activity, the highest human occupation. For the ancients this noble purposelessness
characterized not art alone, but all intellectual activities.
For Schiller more
than two millennia later human beings are motivated by both a constantly
mutating sensuous drive (sinnliche Trieb) arising from physical stimuli
and an unchanging structural drive (Formtrieb) which, like mathematics,
leads toward the rational. [4] For him
the dialectic of these opposing tendencies is resolved through the play drive (der
Spieltrieb), which mediates between the world of phenomena and that of
ideas.
The sensuous
drive excludes all independent activity and freedom from its subject, the
passive receiver of sense data, while the structural drive, situated in the
conceptual realm, excludes all dependence and all pain from its purely formal
values. The exclusion of freedom reflects
a physical reality, while the exclusion of suffering is a spiritual inspiration.
Both drives therefore involve the mind, the one through natural laws, the other
through cognitive operations. In the
play instinct both work together, and, when one is led both by inclination and
by reason to love another individual (or, likewise, an objet d’art) the
synthesis generates a playful attachment in which coercion has no part.
Building on these
conclusions in the twentieth century Johan Huizinga in his Homo Ludens
derives art from play while accepting the biological origins of a play instinct
in “the habitual tendency of every living creature to leap; and the human
creature, by acquiring, as we said, a sense of rhythm, generated and brought
forth dancing ; and since the rhythm is suggested and awakened by the tune, the
union of these.” For Huizinga “rhythm and harmony,” surely mathematical
elements Schiller would have considered “formal,” are “invariably accompanied
by pleasure.” (263)
He usefully
defines the nature of play, listing five distinguishing characteristics.
1.
“Play is free, it is in fact freedom.” (8)
2.
Play is separated from the rest of experience. It is a wholly voluntary activity.
3.
Play is isolated from other activities both in duration and location.
4.
Play “creates order; it is order.” “It is invested with the noblest qualities we
are capable of perceiving in things: rhythm and harmony.” (10) “All play has its rules.” (11)
5.
Play is connected with no functional end whatsoever beyond
recreation. “It interrupts the
appetitive process.” (9)
On this basis he
concludes that Poetry “is born in and as
play – sacred play, no doubt, but always, even in its sanctity, verging on gay
abandon, mirth and jollity.” (122) He proceeds to provide anthropological data
to support the conclusion that myth, art, and religion are all founded in
play. While “Poiesis is, in fact, a
play function,” (119), he notes that poetry sometimes rises to the level of “ideation and judgment,” but “music never
leaves the play sphere.” (158)
Though the
similarity is profound, distinctions remain between the frisking lamb and the
balletomane, the Superbowl fan and the cinemaphile. All may be said to be playing, but only the
film and dance aficionados are engaged with art. The unique aspect of art is that its play
involves manipulating symbols and patterns rather than objects or other
creatures. In this way art is
distinguished from such human activities with no end other than pleasure, such
as travel, gourmet dining, and certain sexual encounters, each of which depends
on stimuli more substantial than the play of images and ideas in the mind. In most music and much dance and abstract
painting the gap is even greater, as the formal design of the work dominates
while reference to the world of lived reality is absent or slight.
Further, whereas
in play one amuses oneself and only possibly fellow players or perhaps a
bemused parent, art is typically made by one individual (in a process that may
or may not be subjectively pleasant) and then consumed by others.
Play is open-ended while art aims at a coherent unified object, finished
in some sense and an artifact thereafter whereas non-aesthetic play is
generally forgotten after it is enacted.
Finally, the rules for art are remade with every work, while those of
chess or a game of catch are unchanging.
Art, then, is a
recreational amusement, a way to pass the time while waiting to die. Its primary end is always pleasure. In this a play by Sophocles and the “playing”
of a violin resemble the “play” of bridge players or that of
frisking kids in a meadow of sweet grass. The painter may wish to make money
and the gallery goer may consider his purchase an investment, but art is in its
essence free of motive outside itself. It is born of
the exhilarating exercise of the human expertise at the manipulation of symbols
when done for its own sake, or rather purely for fun and, with the more sublime
works, perhaps some moments of that satisfying (if mysterious) sort of fun experienced as mental
equipoise.
Artists build
symbolic structures in the chambers of the imagination. Beyond giving pleasure the works they create
can, though their beauty and their order, serve as a “supreme fiction” (in
Stevens’ term) redeeming a world known imperfectly, in fragments, and too often
laden with suffering. Art may realize
that grand ambition or it may simply serve as diversion (doubtless itself a
useful goal). In a dark theater members
of the audience amuse themselves with the play of entering another
consciousness. In an easy chair one
reads a sonnet of Shakespeare and enjoys playing that, one day someone may
spoken such lines direct from the heart, though the reader knows it is all
make-believe. The universality of both
play and the entire spectrum of art – poetry, drama, music, sculpture, dance,
and painting – throughout the world and in all ages, among hunter-gatherers and
among urbanites, demonstrates the critical value of such activities in making
human life livable.
1. David Brooks, “How
to Save a Sad, Lonely, Angry and Mean Society,” New York Times January
28, 2024. Note the. Brooks, a Yale professor but not a literary
scholar, would have agreed for the most part with James Seaton’s Literary
Criticism from Plato to Postmodernism (2016), the most compelling
exposition of the humanistic value of literature in recent years.
2. Poetics
1448b μιμεῖσθαι σύμφυτον τοῖς ἀνθρώποις, ἐκ παίδων ἐστὶ καὶ τούτῳ διαφέρουσι τῶν ἄλλων ζῴων and
“κατὰ φύσιν δὲ ὄντος ἡμῖν τοῦ μιμεῖσθαι.” The word for pleasure, which appears
in this passage in several forms, is “ἡδύς.”
3. Politics
1337b. Note also the origin of school in
σχολή, meaning “leisure” or “that in which leisure is employed.” Such men could, of course, attain freedom
only by depending on slaves to perform the labor to support them.
4. Friedrich Schiller, Über die ästhetische Erziehung des
Menschen in einer Reihe von Briefen (On the Aesthetic Education of Man),
letters twelve through Fourteen. The
quoted lines are in letter fourteen.
No comments:
Post a Comment