Though philosophy
today is most often regarded as an abstruse special interest which, indeed, struggles
to survive even within academia, this isolation is distinctly modern. If one sees the end of philosophy as the search
for a formula for leading the best possible life, it is clearly a matter for
everyone’s consideration. If
philosophical speculation is aimed at a determination of ethics, it is likewise
a subject that engages all people. The
goal of understanding one’s place in the
cosmos or getting some sense of ultimate reality has been ceded to
religion. Yet we understand that in
ancient Athens Socrates plied his trade in public places, the gymnasia and the
agora, always a devoted amateur, and in such places made a name and attracted
followers and challengers. General
interest in philosophy and skill with words became sufficient to support a
class of teachers, the sophists, who, unlike Socrates, were professionals whose
tutelage came at a price. In one
Platonic dialogue, Protagoras, traditionally regarded as the first sophist,
engages wits with Socrates before an audience of over twenty onlookers who
probably would have considered such an encounter as a world-class contest of
ideas, as worthy of watching as the Olympics.
From their disputation two motives for philosophic training emerge that
suggest that intellectual training has value for everyone.
The course of
their dialogue suggests several purposes for philosophic thought, though the
putative topic under discussion is a somewhat different theme: whether virtue
is teachable. These days few would think
of justifying the work of philosophers by its value in furthering social ends,
since their expertise seems irrelevant to the lives of most citizens. Yet Protagoras claims that that he can
“promise to make men good citizens” [1], only for Socrates to object, saying
that social decisions are made by everyone together, regardless of profession,
and neither any individual nor any particular profession has particular
expertise in statecraft.
Of course, in
Classical antiquity, skill in logic and rhetoric was closely associated with deliberative
and forensic arenas, either the assembly and other governmental forums or the
courts. Not only did every free Athenian
male have a voice in deciding issues of the common good, but, for those engaged
in litigation or legal defense, the jury system made persuasiveness of cardinal
importance. Today a mere vote is thought
to be all an individual owes the state, though some will go so far as to write an
occasional letter to the editor or to put out an election yard sign. Yet in the view of the ancient Greeks (and
the founders of the United States), a healthy democracy requires fuller participation
by all, apart from slaves, foreigners, and women. The disastrous recent American election of a would-be
dictator, propelled to power by uneducated voters, reveals the hazards of an
ignorant population.
For the Greeks a
man’s identity was largely constituted by his political role, and the necessity
of sound reasoning by the populace is required for a healthy, well-functioning democracy. Moreover, the training that qualified one to
formulate one’s views in a coherent and convincing way and present persuasive
arguments when discussing legislation or pleading a legal case, is applicable
in many arenas of life. The ability to manipulate symbols is the
distinguishing characteristic of our species.
The general intellectual skills of taking in information, analyzing it,
and producing astute responses are, of course, critical in all endeavors requiring
thought and judgement. Often in our era,
with the decay of debating as a common practice in American secondary schools
and philosophy classes on that level virtually non-existent and ignored by mot
collegians, the development of even fundamental proficiency in thinking and
self-expression is left to the belated attention of those who teach freshman
English classes in universities. Whether
one engaged with a professional teacher like Protagoras or simply a talkative
figure familiar about town like Socrates, the Greeks’ system may have been more
effective at encouraging a generally educated populace, more capable in their
civic role and in private life as well. The
assumption that every person should possess logical and verbal skills is so
strong that people are suspicious of sophists who claim a special expertise and
work for hire, and Protagoras concedes that some think ill of professionals
like himself, though he is willing to proudly affirm his profession in spite of
the “malice and ill-will” and “intrigues” of their critics [2].
In Plato’s Protagoras
Socrates is pleased to be able to meet with Protagoras, ostensibly to gain
wisdom from him, but the reader
suspects, even more to enhance his own reputation by showing up a rival in
philosophical argumentation. The
traditional subtitle of “On the Sophists” suggests a focus on evaluating those
who teach logic and speaking professionally, so, though the general topic is
whether virtue may be taught, the rivalry of Socrates and Protagoras provides
the drama.
In the end, as in
other Platonic dialogues, especially early ones, most of the logical
argumentation has been negative, indicating that received ideas are flawed yet
providing no definitive alternative answer to settle the question. The reader, along with Protagoras and
Socrates’ friends, is left wondering. In the Meno this process, at the heart of
much Platonic ἔλεγχος, is described as a beneficial in itself [3], though in
that dialogue aporia is simply a way-station preceding truth. In the Protagoras there is no further
resolution. The discussion can dislodge
error, but it makes little attempt to formulate a correct answer. What, then, is the point?
Greek philosophy
offers several options to avoid the cul-de-sac of finding a desired answer
unknowable. In Stoicism suspended
judgement, or ἐποχή, is appropriate for some sense experiences (φαντασίαι),
while others are sufficiently convincing as to be kataleptic or “graspable.” [4] For Skeptics, however, particularly the
Pyrrhonist variety, all impressions are doubtful, but in withholding assent and
denial alike, the individual might find a serene mental state or ἀταραξία, following
the recognition that nothing can be certainly known. Here, in a mysterious reversal, not-knowing
is transformed into enlightenment.
Both Plato’s Protagoras,
though, and his Socrates seem clearly to be in pursuit of answers. They are also competitors as providers of
wisdom, and each is characterized as polite yet jealous of his reputation. So the reader might imagine Socrates here as
elsewhere playing devil’s advocate for the more vigorous play of ideas and the
chance to display his ratiocination to greater advantage. He may care more about out-talking Protagoras
than in finding Truth. The discussion is
civil and good-humored, more in the nature of a friendly game of cards than an
angry argument. The audience listens to
both and the conversation, enjoying the spectacle, making the event resemble an
athletic contest or a dramatic production, both of which encode tensions and
antagonisms in a generally harmonious form.
In the last
analysis, the Greeks at Callias’ [5] house were passing the time of day,
amusing themselves with intellectual calisthenics that they found pleasurable
for their own sake, without necessarily coming to a conclusion or uncovering
new knowledge, a form of play very like attending the theater, a foot-race, or
any other diversion. What makes
philosophy superlatively entertaining is that human cognitive skill, the
ability to deal in subtle symbols and recombine words in ever new combinations
, is the distinguishing characteristic of our species. The speakers and the audience in the Protagoras
are doing neither more nor less than having fun with their brains. So philosophy here is a sort of highest level
divertissement with no further end in view than the kitten has when tossing
a stuffed mouse, the dog in retrieving a stick, people idly chatting over a backyard
fence, or while sitting on barstools.
Though neither
good citizenship nor amusement is likely to occur to people today as motives
for philosophy, their endurance in antiquity is suggested by the fact that both
are cited by Cicero three hundred years after Plato. In his Tusculan Disputations he argues
that civilization itself is the result of philosophy, allowing people to live
together in large numbers. He then notes
that some come to the Olympic Games to compete, while others come to sell their
goods to the crowds, and yet a third group come simply to look on, for the sake
of the spectacle. This last, he says,
resembles philosophers, who observe life itself, purely out of curiosity,
because they wish to “look with interest into the nature of things.” [6]
Philosophy as an
enabler of democracy and as an entertainment may seem to have little in common,
even to be opposed: one seems serious, even lofty, aiming toward the betterment
of society, while the other might appear frivolous and trivial, simple amusement. Yet casual conversations such as that
depicted in the Protagoras form the basis for close ties among
fellow-citizens while providing practice in ratiocination and communication
that can equally serve the larger community in legislative and legal deliberation. Philosophy here represents a shared belief
that people do have common problems and a common language for inquiring after
solutions, and that the quest for knowledge is a primary human pleasure,
whether or not anyone ever can arrive at the Truth.
Practice in
thinking, analyzing, understanding, writing, and speaking had been the basis
for all education for millennia. We
moderns can deplore, though we cannot change, the contemporary destruction of
the ideal of a liberal education and the transformation of post-secondary
schooling into vocational training.
Perhaps a rebirth of philosophic studies justified by social utility or
the pure fun of it might rejuvenate our stricken American political culture and
reawaken people to the joys and benefits of juggling concepts.
1. ὑπισχνεῖσθαι ποιεῖν
ἄνδρας ἀγαθοὺς πολίτας 319a.
2. In Greek the terms
are φθόνοι and δυσμένειαί (316d).
3. See Meno
(84c) “Isn’t this numbing then a good
thing?” (ὤνητο ἄρα ναρκήσας;).
4. Epictetus, Discourses
1.18.1 maintains that all human decisions originate in “feeling,” including the
suspension of judgment associated with uncertainty. Thus the ignorant are not to be blamed for
their errors.
5. According to numerous
authorities (Andocides, 130, Aristophanes, The Frogs, v. 432, Athenaeus,
iv. 67; and Aelian, Varia Historia, iv. 16 as well as Plato Apology
20a), Callias is said to have spent his patrimony in support of sophists and
ended his life in penury.
6. Book V, section 5 for
the growth of civilization and V, 9 for the
disinterested inquirer into truth, acting out of curiosity. In this latter passage the relevant Latin phrases
are “sed visendi causa venirent studioseque perspicerent, quid ageretur et quo
modo” (“but come to visit to see what was going on and how”). It is these who “rerum naturam studiose
intuerentur” (“look with interest into the nature of things”).
No comments:
Post a Comment